Page 27 - Studio International - December 1970
P. 27

fenétre  of 1914 or the painting entitled  La   which is rather what treating what is depicted   extended but non-spatial elements.
          Fenêtre, alternatively Le Rideau Jaune, of 1915.   through the frame of the window as mere   The third painting that I want to consider is
          In the painting before us we discern, amongst   ground implies. A view is—of course in a   one of Rothko's canvases from the  Four
          other things, Matisse's recurrent concern with   rather special, one might say in a rather pro-  Seasons series, now hanging in the Tate; to my
          the nature of the ground. Now, if we consider   fessional sense—an object. And now we have a   mind, one of the sublimest creations of our
          what is not so much the earliest painting we   secondary use that Matisse makes of the   time. In comparison with Louis, even with
          have, though it is often called that, as the   surface. For, by emphasizing the surface   Matisse, Rothko's use of the surface is highly
          precursor of painting—I refer to the cave art   where it coincides with the ground, he en-  complex. And I shall only give one hint of
          of the Early Stone Age—there is no ground,   courages this way of looking at or considering   how we might think of this. The greatness of
          there is simply the image.3  With the intro-  the view. The physicality of the surface sug-  Rothko's painting lies ultimately, I am quite
          duction of the ground, the problem arises,   gests, though in a non-representational way,   sure, in its expressive quality, and if we
          How are we to conceive of the ground in a   the physicality of the view. Of course,   wanted to characterize this quality—it would
          way that does not simply equate it with the   Matisse isn't a clumsy painter, and he avoids   be a crude characterization—we would talk,
          gap between the figures or the absence of   that use of the surface which would make it   I am sure, of a form of suffering and of
          depiction ? In the history of European painting   look as though the open window were filled   sorrow, and somehow barely or fragilely con-
          we can see various answers to this question.   with a solid object. It is made clear, at one   tained. We would talk perhaps of some senti-
          One answer is to equate the ground with the   and the same time, that the view isn't an   ment akin to that expressed in Shakespeare's
          background or, if this term is taken broadly   object, but that it is as though it were.   The Tempest—I don't mean, expressed in any one
          enough, the 'landscape', and then for the   The second painting I want to consider is one   character, but in the play itself. However, the
          painter to organize the detail that this equa-  of Morris Louis's late canvases. Louis's work   immediacy of Rothko's canvas derives from
          tion is likely to impose upon him in a hier-  at this stage was largely dominated by one   the way in which this expressive quality is
          archical fashion, detail subsumed within   preoccupation—apart, that is, from his interest   provided with a formal counterpart; and that
          detail, in a Chinese box-like fashion. This   in the physical look of the picture or how the   lies in the uncertainty that the painting is
          answer we can see as given in some of the   surface looks. And this preoccupation can be   calculated to produce, whether we are to see
          finest achievements of European art—for    described from two different points of view.   the painting as containing an image within it
          instance, in such different kind of work as   From one point of view, it is a concern with   or whether we are to see the painting as itself
          that of van Eyck or Poussin. Another answer   colour: from another point of view it is a   an image. Whether we are to see it as contain-
          is to regard the ground as providing, still   concern with patches—where patches are con-  ing a ring of flame or shadow—I owe this
          through representation, not so much content   trasted both with volumes, which are three-  description of the fugitive image to the bril-
          additional to the central figures, but a space   dimensional, and with shapes, which, though   liant description of the Four Seasons paintings
          in which the central figures are framed. Now,   two-dimensional, are seen as suspended in,   by Michel Butor in his essay `Rothko: The
          for a variety of reasons, neither of these two   or visibly inhabit, three-dimensional space.   Mosques of New York'5—or whether we are to
          classic answers is open to Matisse. For    Louis, in other words, wanted to introduce   look upon it as somewhat the equivalent of a
          Matisse—and here he exhibits two of the main   colour into the content of his paintings, but   stained-glass window.°
          thrusts of twentieth-century art—dispenses   to as great a degree as is humanly possible—or,   Now, it is to bring about this uncertainty, as
          both with the notion of detail in the tradi-  better, visibly possible— he wanted considera-  well as to preserve it from, or to prevent it
          tional sense and also with the commitment   tion of the spatial relations between the   from degenerating into a mere oscillation of
          to a unitary and ordered spatial framework.   coloured elements, or the bearers of colour, to   perception, which could, if I am right, be
          And so the question returns, How is the    recede. Now, I do not think that it is quite   highly inimical to Rothko's expressive pur-
          ground to be conceived of— except in purely   correct to say—as Michael Fried does in his   pose, that he uses the surface as he does. For
          negative terms, i.e. as vacancy? How—which   otherwise perceptive account of these paint-  the use of the surface, or the way it manifests
          is an extension of this question—is the frontier   ings4—that Louis's patches are non-repre-  itself to us, simultaneously suggests forms
          of the ground, or the line which encloses it,   sentational: that is to say, I do not think that   within the painting and imposes a unity
          not to seem quite arbitrary? And it is at this   Louis wants us to see 'exclusively' stained parts   across the painting. It suggests light falling
          point, to find an answer to this question, that   of the canvas. He seeks a form of representa-  upon objects and light shining through a
          Matisse resorts to the surface. It is here that   tion where the representation of space or of   translucent plane. Wherever a definitive
          he uses the surface. For what he does is to   anything spatial is at a minimum. And to   reading begins to form itself, the assertion of
          associate the ground so closely with the surface   achieve this effect, he uses the canvas in such   surface calls it in doubt.
          —by which I mean that he charges the surface   a way that while we look centrally at one of   It is only now, when we have taken note of
          in such a way that it barely involves a shift of   the patches we see it representationally. But   other or more working aspects of the theory
          attention for us to move from seeing a certain   as our eyes move towards the edge of the   of modern art as I have suggested it, that it
          expanse as ground to seeing it as surface—that   patch, the representational element dimini-  seems to me appropriate to observe an aspect
          we fully accept the size of the surface as   shes, and we become dominantly, then    that might have seemed to some worthy of
          determining the extent of the ground. The   exclusively, aware of the canvas. In other   earlier attention: I mean the way it is likely
          ground ends, and it seems natural that it   words, representation gets negated at the   to give rise to objects that manifest the only
          should, where the surface ends. To under-  very point where questions of spatiality—how   kind of beauty we find acceptable today.  q
          stand Matisse's use of the surface, we might   does this patch stand to the next?—would
          say that through it he reconciles us to the   begin to arise. The overall effect is that, in   1   See Stanley Cavell  Must We Mean What We Say? (New
                                                                                               York 1969) pp 220-1.
          ground without our hankering after any of the   looking at Louis's patches, we seem aware of   2   E.g. Studio International, Vol. 180, No. 924 ( July-August
          classic ways of treating the ground that   them as though they were embedded in, or   1970) passim.
          Matisse has foresworn.                    pressed down upon, the surface—an effect,   3   On this, see Meyer Schapiro, 'On Some Problems in
          There is perhaps another line of thought in La   which, incidentally, we find, in a highly   the Semiotics of Visual Art: Field and Vehicle in
                                                                                               Image-Signs', Semiotica, Vol. I, No. 3,1969, pp 223-42.
          Fenétre Ouverte which is worth pursuing. What   figurative context, in some of Goya's can-  4   Michael Fried, Three American Painters (Boston, 1965),
          we see through the open window is a view.   vases. The surface, then, is used to control or
                                                                                               pp 19-20.
          Now, at any rate for a painter there is, per-  to limit the operation of representation, so   5   Michel Butor, Inventory  (London 1970).
          haps, a certain absurdity in thinking of a view   that colour can be encountered in what we   6   I have benefited greatly from conversations with Peter
          as a view on to—well, as a view on to nothing,    might call a 'pure' mode : as predicated of    Larisey, S. J., on this point.
   22   23   24   25   26   27   28   29   30   31   32